3. SYSTEMS INQUIRY AND ITS APPLICATION IN EDUCATION
Bela H. Banathy
INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS INSTITUTE
3.1 PART 1: SYSTEMS INQUIRY
The first part of this chapter is a review of the evolution of the systems
movement and a discussion of human systems inquiry.
3. 1. 1 A Definition of Systems Inquiry
Systems inquiry incorporates three interrelated domains of disciplined
inquiry: systems theory, systems philosophy, and systems methodology.
Bertalanffy (1968) notes that in contrast with the analytical, reductionist,
and linear-causal paradigm of classical science, systems philosophy brings
forth a reorientation of thought and world view, manifested by an expansionist,
nonlinear dynamic, and synthetic mode of thinking. The scientific exploration
of systems theories and the development of systems theories in the various
sciences have brought forth a general theory of systems, a set of interrelated
concepts and principles, applying to all systems. Systems methodology
provides us with a set of models, strategies, methods, and tools that
instrumentalize systems theory and philosophy in analysis, design, development,
and management of complex systems.
3.1.1.1. Systems Theory. During the early 1950s, the basic concepts
and principles of a general theory of systems were set forth by such pioneers
of the systems movement as Ashby, Bertalanffy, Boulding, Fagen, Gerard,
Rappoport, and Wienner. They came from a variety of disciplines and fields
of study. They shared and articulated a common conviction: the unified
nature of reality. They recognized a compelling need for a unified disciplined
inquiry in understanding and dealing with increasing complexities that
are beyond the competence of any single discipline. As a result, they
developed a transdisciplinary perspective that emphasized the intrinsic
order and interdependence of the world in all its manifestations. From
their work emerged systems theory, the science of complexity. In defining
systems theory, I review the key ideas of Bertalatiffy and Boulding, who
were two of the founders of the Society for the Advancement of General
Systems Theory. Later, the name of the society was changed to the Society
for General Systems Research, then the International Society for Systems
research, and recently to the International Society for the Systems Sciences.
3.1.1.1.1. Bertalanffy (1956, pp. 1-10). He suggested that "modem
science is characterized by its ever-increasing specialization, necessitated
by the enormous amount of data, the complexity of techniques, and structures
within every field. This, however, led to a breakdown of science as an
integrated realm. "Scientists, operating in the various disciplines,
are encapsulated in their private universe, and it is difficult to get
word from one cocoon to the other." Against this background, he observes
a remarkable development, namely, that "similar general viewpoints
and conceptions have appeared in very different fields." Reviewing
this development in those fields, Bertalatiffy suggests that there exist
models, principles, and laws that can be generalized across various systems,
their components, and the relationships among them. "It seems legitimate
to ask for a theory, not of systems of a more or less special kind, but
of universal principles applying to systems in general."
The first consequence of this approach is the recognition of the existence
of systems properties that are general and structural similarities or
isomorphies in different fields:
There are correspondences in the principles which govern the
behavior of entities that are intrinsically widely different. These correspondences
are due to the fact that they all can be considered, in certain aspects,
"systems," that is, complexes of elements standing in interaction.
[It seems] that a general theory of systems would be a useful tool providing,
on the one hand, models that can be used in, and transferred to, different
fields, and safeguarding, on the other hand, from vague analogies which
often have marred the progress in these fields.
The second consequence of the idea of a general theory is to deal with
organized complexity, which is a main problem of modem science.
Concepts like those of organization, wholeness, directiveness,
teleology, control, self-regulation, differentiation, and the like are
alien to conventional science. However, they pop up everywhere in the
biological, behavioral, and social sciences and are, in fact, indispensable
for dealing with living organisms or social groups. Thus, a basic problem
posed to modem science is a general theory of organization. General Systems
Theory is, in principle, capable of giving exact definitions for such
concepts.
Thirdly, Bertalanffy suggested that it is important to say what a general
theory of systems is not. It is not identical with the triviality of mathematics
of some sort that can be applied to any sort of problems; instead "it
poses special problems that are far from being trivial." It is not
a search for superficial analogies between physical, biological,
and social systems. The isomorphy we have mentioned is a consequence of
the fact that, in certain aspects, corresponding abstractions and conceptual
models can be applied to different phenomena. It is only in view of these
aspects that system laws apply.
Bertalanffy summarizes the aims of a general theory of systems as follows:
(a) There is a general tendency towards integration in the various
sciences, natural and social. (b) Such integration seems to be centered
in a general theory of systems. (c) Such theory may be an important means
of aiming at exact theory in the nonphysical fields of science. (d) Developing
unifying principles running "vertically" through the universe
of the individual sciences, this theory brings us nearer to the goal of
the unity of sciences. (e) This can lead to a much needed integration
in scientific education.
Commenting later on education, Bertalanffy noted that education treats
the various scientific disciplines as separate domains, where increasingly
smaller subdomains become separate sciences, unconnected with the rest.
In contrast, the educational demands of scientific generalists and developing
transdisciplinary basic principles are precisely those that General Systems
Theory (GST) tries to fill. In this sense, GST seems to make an important
headway toward transdisciplinary synthesis and integrated education.
3.1.1.1.2. Boulding (1956, pp. 11-17). He underscored the need for a
general theory as he suggested that in recent years increasing need has
been felt for a body of theoretical constructs that will discuss the general
relationships of the empirical world.
This is the quest of General Systems Theory (GST). It does not seek,
of course, to establish a single, self-contained "general theory
of practically everything" which will, replace all the special
theories of particular disciplines. Such a theory would be almost without
content, and all we can say about practically everything is almost nothing.
Somewhere between the specific that has no meaning and the general
that has no content there must be, for each purpose and at each level
of abstraction, an optimum degree of generality.
The objectives of GST, then, can be set out with varying degrees of ambitions
and confidence. At a low level of ambition, but with a high degree of
confidence, it aims to point out similarities in the theoretical constructions
of different disciplines, where these exist, and to develop theoretical
models having applicability to different fields of study. At a higher
level of ambition, but perhaps with a lower level of confidence, it hopes
to develop something like a "spectrum" of theories-a system
of, systems that may perform a "gestalt" in theoretical constructions.
It is the main objective of GST, says Boulding, to develop "generalized
ears" that overcome the "specialized deafness" of the specific
disciplines, meaning that someone who ought to know something that someone
else knows isn't able to find it out for lack of generalized ears. Developing
a framework of a general theory will enable the specialist to catch relevant
communications from others.
In the closing section of his paper, Boulding referred to the subtitle
of his paper: GST as "the skeleton of science." It is a skeleton
in the sense-he says-that:
It aims to provide a framework or structure of systems on which
to hang the flesh and blood of particular disciplines and particular subject
matters in an orderly and coherent corpus of knowledge. It is also, however,
something of a skeleton in a cupboard-the cupboard in this case being
the unwillingness of science to admit the tendency to shut the door on
problems and subject matters which do not fit easily into simple mechanical
schemes. Science, for all its success, still has a very long way to go.
GST may at times be an embarrassment in pointing out how very far we still
have to go, and in deflating excessive philosophical claims for overly
simple systems. It also may be helpful, however, in pointing out to some
extent where we have to go. The skeleton must come out of the cupboards
before its dry bones can live.
The two papers introduced above set forth the "vision" of the
systems movement. That vision still guides us today. At this point it
seems to be appropriate to tell the story that marks the genesis of the
systems movement. Kenneth Boulding told this story at the occasion when
I was privileged to present to him the distinguished scholarship award
of the Society of General Systems Research at our 1983 Annual Meeting.
The year was 1954. At the Center for Behavioral Sciences, at Stanford
University, four Center Fellows-Bertalanffy (biology), Boulding (economics),
Gerard (psychology), and Rappoport (mathematics)-had a discussion in a
meeting room. Another Center Fellow walked in and asked: "What's
going on here?" Ken answered: "We are angered about the state
of the human condition and ask: 'What can we-what can science-do about
improving the human condition?"' "Oh!" their visitor said:
"This is not my field. . . ." At that meeting the four scientists
felt that in the statement of their visitor they heard the statement of
the fragmented disciplines that have little concern for doing anything
practical about the fate of humanity. So, they asked themselves, "What
would happen if science would be redefined by crossing disciplinary boundaries
and forge a general theory that would bring us together in the service
of humanities? Later they went to Berkeley, to the annual meeting of the
American Association for the Advancement of Science, and established the
Society for the Advancement of General Systems Theory. Throughout the
years, many of us in the systems movement have continued to ask the question:
How can systems science serve humanity?
3.1.1.2. Systems Philosophy. The next main branch of systems inquiry
is systems philosophy. Systems philosophy is concerned with a systems
view of the world and the elucidation of systems thinking as an approach
to theoretical and real-world problems. Systems philosophy seeks to uncover
the most general assumptions lying at the roots of any and all of systems
inquiry. An articulation of these assumptions gives systems inquiry coherence
and internal consistency. Systems philosophy (Laszlo, 1972) seeks to probe
the basic texture and ultimate implications of systems inquiry. It "guides
the imagination of the systems scientist and provides a general world
view, the likes of which-in the history of science-has proven to be the
most significant for asking the right question and perceiving the relevant
state of affairs" ( p. 10). The general scientific nature of systems
inquiry implies its direct association with philosophy. This explains
the philosophers' early and continuing interest in systems theory and
the early and continuing interest of systems theorists and methodologists
in the philosophical aspects of systems inquiry. In general, philosophical
aspects are worked out in two directions. The first involves inquiry into
the What: what things are, what a person or a society is, and what kind
of world we live in. These questions pertain to what we call ontology.
The second question is How: How do we know what we know; how do we know
what kind of world we live in; how do we know what kind of persons we
are? The exploration of these questions are the domain of epistemology.
One might differentiate these two, but, as Bateson (1972) noted, ontology
and epistemology cannot be separated. Our beliefs about what the world
is will determine how we see it and act within it. And our ways of perceiving
and acting will determine our beliefs about its nature. Blauberg, Sadovsky,
and Yudin (1977) noted that the philosophical aspects of systems inquiry
would give us an "unequivocal solution to all or most problems arising
from a study of systems" (p. 94).
3.1.1.2.1. Ontology. The ontological task is the formation of a systems
view of what is-in the broadest sense a systems view of the world. This
can lead to a new orientation for scientific inquiry. As Baluberg (1977)
noted, this orientation emerged into a holistic view of the world. Waddington
(1977) presents a historical review of two great philosophical alternatives
of the intellectual picture we have of the world. One view is that the
world essentially consists of things. The other view is that the world
consists of processes, and the things are only "stills" out
of the moving picture. Systems philosophy developed as the main rival
of the "thing view." It recognizes the primacy of organizing
relationship processes between entities (of systems), from which emerge
the novel properties of systems.
3.1.1.2.2. Epistemology. This philosophical aspect deals with general
questions: How do we know whatever we know? How do we know what kind of
world we live in and what kind of organisms we are? What sort of thing
is the mind? Bateson (1972) notes that originating from systems theory,
extraordinary advances have been made in answering these questions. The
ancient question of whether the mind is immanent or transcendent can be
answered in favor of immanence. Furthermore, any ongoing ensemble (system)
that has the appropriate complexity of causal and energy relationships
will: (a) show mutual characteristics, (b) compare and respond to differences,
(c) process information, (d) be self-corrective, and (e) no part of an
internally interactive system can exercise unilateral control over other
parts of the system. "The mutual characteristics of a system are
immanent not in some part, but in the system as a whole" (p. 316).
The epistemological aspects of systems philosophy address: (a) the principles
of how systems inquiry is conducted; (b) the specific categorical apparatus
of the inquiry, and that connected with it; and (c) the theoretical language
of systems science. The most significant guiding principle of systems
inquiry is that of giving prominence to synthesis, not only as the culminating
activity of the inquiry (following analysis) but also as a point of departure.
This approach to the "how do we know" contrasts with the epistemology
of traditional science that is almost exclusively analytical.
3.1.1.3. Systems Methodology. Systems methodology- vital part
of systems inquiry-has two domains of inquiry: (1) the study of methods
in systems investigations by which we generate knowledge about systems
in general and (2) the identification and description of strategies, models,
methods, and tools for the application of systems theory and systems thinking
for working with complex systems. In the context of this second domain,
systems methodology is a set of coherent and related methods and tools
applicable to: (a) the analysis of systems and systems problems, problems
concerned with the systemic/ relational aspects of complex systems; (b)
the design, development, implementation, and evaluation of complex systems;
and (c) the management of systems and the management of change in systems.
The task of those using systems methodology in a given context is threefold:
(1) to identify, characterize, and classify the nature of the problem
situation, i.e., (a), (b), or (c) above; (2) to identify and characterize
the problem context and content in which the methodology is applied; (3)
to identify and characterize the type of system in which the problem situation
is embedded; and (4) to select specific strategies, methods, and tools
that are appropriate to the nature of the problem situation, to the context/content,
and to the type of systems in which the problem situation is located.
The brief discussion above highlights the difference between the methodology
of systems inquiry and the methodology of scientific inquiry in the various
disciplines.
The methodology of a discipline is clearly defined and is to be adhered
to rigorously. It is the methodology that is the hallmark of a discipline.
In systems inquiry, on the other hand, one selects methods and methodological
tools or approaches that best fit the nature of the identified problem
situation, and the context, the content, and the type of system that is
the domain of the investigation. The methodology is to be selected from
a wide range of systems methods that are available to us.
3.1.1.4. The Interaction of the Domains of Systems Inquiry. Systems
philosophy, systems theory, and systems methodology come to life as they
are used and applied in the functional context of systems. It is in the
context of use that they are confirmed, changed, modified, and reconfirmed.
Systems philosophy presents us with the underlying assumptions that provide
the perspectives that guide us in defining and organizing the concepts
and principles that constitute systems theory. Systems theory and systems
philosophy then guide us in developing, selecting, and organizing approaches,
methods, and tools into the scheme of systems methodology. Systems methodology
then is used in the functional context of systems. But this process is
not linear or forward-moving circular. It is recursive and multi-directional
One confirms or modifies the other. As theory is developed, it gets its
confirmation from its underlying assumptions (philosophy), as well as
from its application through methods in functional contexts. Methodology
is confirmed or changed by testing its relevance to its theoretical/philosophical
foundations and by its use. The functional context-the society in general
and systems of all kinds in particular-is a primary source of placing
demands on systems inquiry. It was, in fact, the emergence of complex
systems that brought about the recognition of the need for new scientific
thinking, new theory, and methodologies. It was this need that systems
inquiry addressed and satisfied.
The dynamics of the recursive and multi-directional interaction of the
four domains, described above, makes systems inquiry a living system.
These dynamics are manifested in the interplay between confirmation and
novelty. Novelty at times brings about adjustments and at other times
it appears as discontinuities and major shifts. The process described
here becomes transparent as the evolution of the systems movement is reviewed
next.
3.1.2 Evolution of the Systems Movement
Throughout the evolution of humanity there has been a constant yearning
for understanding the wholeness of the human experience that manifests
itself in the wholeness of the human being and the human society. Wholeness
has been sought also in the disciplined inquiry of science as a way of
searching for the unity of science and a unified theory of the universe.
This search reaches back through the ages into the golden age of Greek
philosophy and science in Plato's kybernetics, the art of steermanship,
which is the origin of modem cybernetics: a domain of contemporary systems
thinking. The search intensified during the Age of Enlightenment and the
Age of Reason and Certainty, and it was manifested in the clockwork mechanistic
world view. The search has continued in the current age of uncertainty
(Heisenberg) and complexity, the science of relativity, (Einstein), quantum
theory (Bohr & Shrodinger), and the theory of wholeness and the implicate
order (Bohm).
In recent years, the major player in this search has been the systems
movement. The genesis of the movement can be timed as the mid-50s (as
discussed at the beginning of this chapter). But prior to that time, we
can account for the emergence of the systems idea through the work of
several philosophers and scientist.
3.1.2.1. The Pioneers. Some of the key notions of systems theory
were articulated by the 18th-century German philosopher Hagel. He suggested
that the whole is more than the sum of its parts, that the whole determines
the nature of the parts, and the parts are dynamically interrelated and
cannot be understood in isolation from the whole.
Most likely, the first person who used the term general theory of systems
was the Hungarian philosopher and scientist Bela Zalai. Zalai, during
the years 1913 to 1914, developed his theory in a collection of papers
called A Rendszerek Altalanos Elmelete. The German translation was entitled
Allgemeine Theorie der Systeme [General Theory of Systems]. The work was
republished (Zalai, 1984) in Hungarian and was recently reviewed in English
(Banathy & Banathy, 1989). In a three-volume treatise, Tektologia,
Bogdanov (1921-1927), a Russian scientist, characterized Tektologia as
a dynamic science of complex wholes, concerned with universal structural
regularities, general types of systems, the general laws of their transformation,
and the basic laws of organization. Bogdanov's work was published in English
by Golerik (1980).
In the decades prior to and during World War 11, the search intensified.
The idea of a General Systems Theory was developed by Bertalanffy in the
late 30s and was presented in various lectures. But his material remained
unpublished until 1945 (Zu einer allgemeinen Systemlehre) followed by
"An Outline of General Systems Theory" (1951). Without using
the term GST, the same frame of thinking was used in various articles
by Ashby during the years 1945 and 1947, published in his book Design
for a Brain, in 1952.
3.1.2.2. Organized Developments. In contrast with the work of
individual scientists, outlined above, since the 1940s we can account
for several major developments that reflect the evolution of the systems
movement, including "hard systems science," cybernetics, and
the continuing evolution of a general theory of systems.
3.1.3 Hard-Systems Science
Under hard-systems science, we can account for two organized developments:
operations research and systems engineering.
3.1.3.1. Operations Research. During the Second World War, it
was again the "functional context" that challenged scientists.
The complex problems of logistics and resource management in waging a
war became the genesis of developing the earliest organized form of systems
science: the quantitative analysis of rather closed systems. It was this
orientation from which operations research and management science emerged
during the 50s. This development directed systems science toward "hard"
quantitative analysis. Operations research flourished during the 60s,
but in the 70s, due to the changing nature of sociotechnical systems contexts,
it went through a major shift toward a less quantitative orientation.
3.1.3.2. Systems Engineering. This is concerned with the design
of closed man-machine systems and larger-scale sociotechnical systems.
Systems engineering (SE) can be portrayed as a system of methods and tools,
specific activities for problem solutions, and a set of relations between
the tools and activities. The tools include language, mathematics, and
graphics by which systems engineering communicates. The content of SE
includes a variety of algorithms and concepts that enable various activities.
The first major work in SE was published by A. D. Hall (1962). He presented
a comprehensive, three-dimensional morphology for systems engineering.
In a more recent work, Sage (1977) has changed the directions of SE.
We use the word system to refer to the application of systems
science and methodologies associated with the science of problem solving.
We use the word engineering not only to mean the mastery and manipulation
of physical data but also to imply social and behavioral consideration
as inherent parts of the engineering design process (p. xi).
During the 60s and early 70s, practitioners of operations research and
systems engineering attempted to transfer their approaches into the context
of social systems. It led to disasters. It was this period when "social
engineering" emerged as an approach to address societal problems.
A recognition of failed attempts have led to changes in direction, best
manifested by the quotation of Sage in the paragraph above.
3.1.4 Cybernetics
Cybernetics is concerned with the understanding of self-organization
of human, artificial, and natural systems; the understanding of understanding;
and its relation and relevance to other transdisciplinary approaches.
Cybernetics, as part of the systems movement, evolved through two phases:
first-order cybernetics, the cybernetics of the observed system, and second-order
cybernetics, the cybernetics of the observing system.
3.1.4.1. First-Order Cybernetics. This early formulation of cybernetics
inquiry was concerned with communication and control in the animal and
the machine (Wiener, 1948). The emphasis on the in allowed focus on the
process of self-organization and self-regulation, on circular causal feedback
mechanisms, together with the systemic principles that underlie them.
These principles underlay the computer/cognitive sciences and are credited
with being at the heart of neural network approaches in computing. The
first-order view treated information as a quantity, as "bits"
to be transmitted from one place to the other. It focused on "noise"
that interfered with smooth transmission (Weatley, 1992). The content,
the meaning, and the purpose of information was ignored (Gleick, 1987).
3.1.4.2. Second-Order Cybernetics. As a concept, this expression
was coined by Foerster (1984), who describes this shift as follows: "We
are now in the possession of the truism that a description (of the universe)
implies one who describes (observes it). What we need now is a description
of the 'describer' or, in other words, we need a theory of the observer"
(p. 258). The general notion of second-order cybernetics is that "observing
systems" awaken the notion of language, culture, and communication
(Brier, 1992); and the context, the content, the meaning, and purpose
of information becomes central. Second-order cybernetics, through the
concept of self-reference, wants to explore the meaning of cognition and
communication within the natural and social sciences, the humanities,
and information science; and in such social practices as design, education,
organization, art, management, and politics, etc. (p. 2).
3.1.5 The Continuing Evolution of Systems Inquiry
The first part of this chapter describes the emergence of the systems
idea and its manifestation in the three branches of systems inquiry: systems
theory, systems philosophy, and systems methodology. This section traces
the evolution of systems inquiry. This evolutionary discussion will be
continued later in a separate section by focusing on "human systems
inquiry."
3.1.5.1. The Continuing Evolution of Systems Thinking. In a comprehensive
report, commissioned by the Society of General Systems Research, Cavallo
(1979) says that systems inquiry shattered the essential features of the
traditional scientific paradigm characterized by analytic thinking, reductionism,
and determinism. The systems paradigm articulates synthetic thinking,
emergence, communication and control, expansionism, and teleology. 'Me
emergence of these core systems ideas was the consequence of a change
of focus, away from entities that cannot be taken apart without loss of
their essential characteristics, and hence can not be truly understood
from analysis.
First, this change of focus gave rise to synthetic or systems thinking
as complementary to analysis. In synthetic thinking an entity to be understood
is conceptualized not as a whole to be taken apart but as a part of one
or more larger wholes. The entity is explained in terms of its function,
and its role in its larger context. Second, another major consequence
of the new thinking is expansionism (an alternative to reductionism),
which asserts that ultimate understanding is an ideal that can never be
attained but can be continuously approached. Progress towards it depends
on understanding ever-larger and more inclusive wholes. Third, the idea
of nondeterministic causality, developed by Singer (1959), made it possible
to develop the notion of objective teleology, a conceptual system in which
such teleological concepts as fire will, choice, function, and purpose
could be operationally defined and incorporated into the domain of science.
3.1.5.2. A General Theory of Dynamic Systems. The theory was
developed by Jantsch (1980). He argues that an emphasis on structure and
dynamic equilibrium (steady-state flow), which characterized the earlier
development of general systems theory, led to a profound understanding
of how primarily technological structures may be stabilized and maintained
by complex mechanisms that respond to negative feedback. (Negative feedback
indicates deviation from established norms and calls for a reduction of
such deviation.) In biological and social systems, however, negative feedback
is complemented by positive feedback, which increases deviation by the
development of new systems processes and forms. The new understanding
that has emerged recognizes such phenomena as self-organization, self-reference,
self-regulation, coherent behavior over time with structural change, individuality,
symbiosis, and coevolution with the environment, and morphogenesis.
This new understanding of systems behavior, says Jantsch, emphasizes
process in contrast to "solid" subsystems structures and components.
The interplay of process in systems leads to evolution of structures.
An emphasis is placed on "becoming," a decisive conceptual breakthrough
brought about by Prigogine (1980). Prigogine's theoretical development
and empirical conformation of the so-called dissipative structures and
his discovery of a new ordering systems principle called order through
fluctuation led to an explication of a "general theory of dynamic
systems."
During the early 80s, a whole range of systems thinking based methodologies
emerged, based on what is called soft systems thinking. These are all
relevant to human and social systems and will be discussed under the heading
of human systems inquiry. In this section, two additional developments
are discussed: systems thinking based on "liberating systems theory"
and "unbounded systems thinking."
3.1.5.3. Liberating Systems Theory(Flood, pp. 210-211, 1990).
This theory is (1) in pursuit of freeing systems theory from certain tendencies
and, in a more general sense, (2) tasking systems theory with liberation
of the human condition. The first task is developed in three trends: (1)
the liberation of systems theory generally from the natural tendency toward
self-imposed insularity, (2) the liberation of systems concepts from objectivist
and subjectivist delusions, and (3) the liberation of systems theory specifically
in cases of internalized localized subjugations in discourse and by considering
histories and progressions of systems thinking. The second task of the
theory focuses on liberation and emancipation in response to domination
and subjugation in work and social situations.
3.1.5.5. Unbounded Systems Thinking(Mitroff & Linstone, 1993).
This development "is the basis for the ,new thinking' called for
in the information age" (p. 91).In unbounded systems thinking (UST),
"everything interacts with everything."
All branches of inquiry depend fundamentally on one another.
The widest possible array of disciplines, professions, and branches of
knowledge capturing distinctly different paradigms of thought-must be
consciously brought to bear on our problems. In UST, the traditional hierarchical
ordering of the sciences and the professions-as well as the pejorative
bifurcation of the sciences into 'hard' vs. 'soft'-is replaced by a circular
concept of relationship between diem. The basis for choosing a particular
way of modeling or representing a problem is not governed merely by considerations
of conventional logic and rationality. It may also involve considerations
of justice and fairness as perceived by various social groups and by consideration
of personal ethics or morality as perceived by distinct persons"
(p. 9).
3.1.5.6. Living Systems Theory. This theory was developed by Miller
(1978) as a continuation and elaboration of the organismic orientation
of Bertalanffy. The theory is a conceptual scheme for the description
and analysis of concrete identifiable living systems. It describes seven
levels of living systems, ranging from the lower levels of cell, organ,
and organism, to higher levels of group, organizations, societies, and
supranational systems.
The central thesis of living systems theory is that at each level a
system is characterized by the same 20 critical subsystems whose processes
are essential to life. A set of these subsystems processes information
(input transducer, internal transducer, channel and net, decoder, associator,
decider, memory, encoder, output transducer, and time). Another set processes
matter and energy (ingestor, distributor, converter, producer, storage,
extruder, motor, and supporter). Two subsystems (reproducer and boundary)
process matter/ energy and information.
Living system theory presents a common framework for analyzing structure
and process and identifying the health and well-being of systems at various
levels of complexity. A set of cross-level hypotheses was identified by
Miller as a basis for conducting such analysis. During the 80s, Living
systems theory has been applied by a method-called living systems process
analysis-to the study of complex problem situations embedded in a diversity
of fields and activities. [Living systems process analysis has been applied
in educational contexts by Banathy and Mills (1988).]
3.1.6 Human Systems Inquiry
Human systems inquiry focuses systems theory, systems philosophy, and
systems methodology and their applications on social or human systems.
This section portrays human systems inquiry as follows: (1) present some
of its basic characteristics, (2) describe the various types of human
or social systems, (3) discuss the nature of problem situations and solutions
in human systems inquiry, and (4) introduce the "soft-systems"
approach and social systems design. The discussion of these issues will
help us appreciate why human systems inquiry must be different from other
modes of inquiry. Furthermore, in as much as education is a human systems
inquiry will lead to our discussion on systems inquiry in education.
3.1.6.1. The Characteristics of Human Systems. Human Systems
Are Different is the title of the last book of the systems philosopher
Geoffrey Vickers (1983). Discussing the characteristics of summary of
their open nature as follows. (1) Open systems are nests of relations
that are sustained through time. They are sustained by these relations
and by the process of regulation. The limits within which they can be
sustained are the conditions of their stability. (2) Open systems depend
on and contribute to their environment. They are dependent on this interaction
as well as on their internal interaction. These interactions/dependencies
impose constraints on all their constituents. Human systems can mitigate
but cannot remove these constraints, which tend to become more demanding
and at times even contradictory as the scale of the organization increases.
This might place a limit on the potential of the organization. (3) Open
systems are wholes, but are also parts of larger systems, and their constituents
may also be constituents of other systems. Change in human systems is
inevitable. Systems adapt to environmental changes, and in a changing
environment this becomes a continuous process. At times, however, adaptation
does not suffice, so the whole system might change. Through coevolution
and cocreation, change between the systems and its environment is a mutual
recursive phenomenon (Buckley, 1968; Jantch, 1976, 1980). Wheatley (1992),
discussing stability, change, and renewal in self-organizing system, remarks
that in the past, scientists focused on the overall structure of systems,
leading them away from understanding the processes of change that makes
a system viable over time. They were looking for stability. Regulatory
(negative) feedback was a way to ensure the stability of systems, to preserve
their current state. They overlooked the function of positive feedback
that moves the system toward change and renewal. Checkland (1981) presents
a comprehensive characterization of what he calls human activity systems
(HASs). HASs are very different from natural and engineered systems. Natural
and engineered systems cannot be other than what they are.
Human activity systems, on the other hand, are manifested through
the perception of human beings who are free to attribute meanings to what
they perceive. There will never be a single (testable) account of human
activity systems, only a set of possible accounts, all valid according
to particular Weltanshaungen (p. 14).
He further says, that HASs are structured sets of people who make up
the system, coupled with a collection of such activities as processing
information, making plans, performing, and monitoring performance.
According to Argyris and Schon (1979), a social group becomes an organization
when members devise procedures for "Making decisions in the name
of the collectivity, delegate of inquiry. Furthermore, inasmuch as education
is a human to individuals the authority to act for the collectivity, and
system, such understanding and a review of approaches to setting boundaries
between the collectivity and the rest of the human systems world"
(p. 13). Ackoff and Emery(1972) characterize human systems as purposeful
systems whose members are also purposeful individuals who intentionally
and collectevely formulate objectives. In human systems, "the state
of the part can be determined only in reference to the state of the system.
The effect of change in one part or another is mediated by changes in
the state of the whole" (p. 218).
Ackoff (1981) suggests that human systems are purposeful systems that
have purposeful parts and are parts of larger purposeful systems.This
observation reveals three fundamental issues, namely, how to design and
manage human systems so that they can effectively and efficiently serve
(1) their own purposes, (2) the purposes of their purposeful parts and
people in the system, and (3) the purposes of the larger system(s) of
which they are part. These functions are called: (1) self-directiveness,
(2) humanization, and (3) environmentalization, respectively. Viewing
human systems from an evolutionary perspective, Jantsch (1980) suggests
that according to the dualistic paradigm, adaptation is a response to
something that evolved outside of the systems. He notes, however, that
with the emergence of the self-organizing paradigm, a scientifically founded
nondualistic view became possible. This view is process oriented and establishes
that evolution is an integral part of self-organization. True self-organization
incorporates self-transcendence, the creative reaching out of a human
system beyond its boundaries. Jantsch concludes that creation is the core
of evolution, it is the joy of life, it is not just adaptation, not just
securing survival. In the final analysis, says Laszlo (1987), social systems
are value-guided systems. Insofar as they are independent of biological
need-fulfillment and reproductive needs, cultures satisfy not body needs
but values. All cultures respond to such suprabiological values. But in
what form they do so depends on the specific kind of values people happen
to have.
3.1.6.2. Types of Human Systems. Human activity systems (HASs),
such as educational systems, are purposeful creations. People in these
systems select, organize, and carry opt activities in order to attain
their purposes. Reviewing the research of Ackoff (1981), Jantsch (1976),
Jackson and Keys (1984), and Southerland (1973), the author developed
a comprehensive classification of HASs (1988) based on: (1) the degree
to which they are open or closed, (2) their mechanistic vs. systemic nature,
(3) their unitary vs. pluralistic position on defining their purpose,and
(4) the degree and nature of their complexity (simple, detailed, dynamic).
Based on these dimensions, we can differentiate five types of HASs: rigidly
controlled, deterministic, purposive, heuristic, and purpose seeking.
3.1.6.2.1. Rigidly Controlled Systems. These systems are rather closed.
Their structure is simple, consisting of few elements with limited interaction
among them. They have a singleness of purpose and clearly defined goals,
and act mechanically. Operational ways and means are prescribed.
There is little room for self-direction. They have a rigid structure
and stable relationship among system components. Examples are assembly-line
systems and man machine systems.
3.1.6.2.2. Deterministic Systems. These are still more closed than open.
They have clearly assigned goals; thus, they are unitary. People in the
system have a limited degree of freedom in selecting methods. Their complexity
ranges from simple to detailed. Examples are bureaucracies, instructional
systems, and national educational.
3.1.6.2.3. Purposive Systems. These are still unitary but are more open
than closed, and react to their environment in order to maintain their
viability. Their purpose is established at the top, but people in the
system have freedom to select operational means and methods. They have
detailed to dynamic complexity. Examples are corporations, social service
agencies, and our public education systems.
3.1.6.2.4. Heuristic Systems. Such systems as R&D agencies and innovative
business ventures formulate their own goals under broad policy guidelines;
thus, they are somewhat pluralistic. They are open to changes and often
initiate changes. Their complexity is dynamic, and their internal arrangements
and operations are systemic. Examples of heuristic systems include innovative
business ventures, educational R&D agencies, and alternative educational
systems.
3.1.6.2.5. Purpose-Seeking Systems. These systems are ideal seeking
and are guided by their vision of the future. They are open and coevolve
with their environment. They exhibit dynamic complexity and systemic behavior.
They are pluralistic, as they constantly seek new purposes and search
for new niches in their environments. Examples are (a) communities seeking
to establish integration of their systems of learning and human development
with social, human, and health service agencies, and their community and
economic development programs, and (b) cutting-edge R&D agencies.
In working with human systems, the understanding of what type of system
we are working with, or the determination of the type of systems we wish
to design, is crucial in that it suggests the selection of the approach
and the methods and tools that are appropriate to systems inquiry.
3.1.7 The Nature of Problem Situations and Solutions
Working with human systems, we are confronted with problem situations
that comprise a system of problems rather than a collection of problems.
Problems are embedded in uncertainty and require subjective interpretation.
Churchman (1971) suggested that in working with human systems, subjectivity
cannot be avoided. What really matters, he says, is that systems are unique,
and the task is to account for their uniqueness; and this uniqueness has
to be considered in their description and design. Our main tool in working
with human systems is subjectivity: reflection on the sources of knowledge,
social practice, community, and interest in and commitment to ideas, especially
the moral idea, affectivity, and faith.
Working with human systems, we must recognize that they are unbounded.
Factors assumed to be part of a problem are inseparably linked to many
other factors. A technical problem in transportation, such as the building
of a freeway, becomes a land-use problem, linked with economic, environmental,
conservation, ethical, and political issues. Can we really draw a boundary?
When we seek to improve a situation, particularly if it is a public one,
we find ourselves facing not a problem but a cluster of problems, often
called problematique. Peccei (1977), the founder of the Club of Rome,
says that:
Within the problematique, it is difficult to pinpoint individual
problems and propose individual solutions. Each problem is related to
every other problem; each apparent solution to a problem may aggravate
or interfere with others; and none of these problems or their combination
can be tackled using the linear or sequential methods of the past"
(p. 6 1).
Ackoff suggests (1981) that a set of interdependent problems constitutes
a system of problems, which he calls a mess. Like any system, the mess
has properties that none of its parts has. These properties are lost when
the system is taken apart. In addition, each part of a system has properties
that are lost when it is considered separately. The solution to a mess
depends on how its parts interact. In an earlier statement, Ackoff (1974)
says that the era of "quest for certainty" has passed. We live
an age of uncertainty in which systems are open, dynamic; in which problems
live in a moving process. "Problems and solutions are in constant
flux, hence problems do not stay solved. Solutions to problems become
obsolete even if the problems to which they are addressed are not"
(p. 31). Ulrich (1983) suggests that when working with human systems,
we should reflect critically on problems. He asks: How can we produce
solutions if the problems remain unquestioned? We should transcend problems
as originally stated and should explore critically the problem itself
with all of those who are affected by the problem. We must differentiate
well-structured and well-defined problems in which the initial conditions,
the goals, and the necessary operations can all be specified, from ill-defined
or ill-structured problems, the kind in which initial conditions, the
goals, and the allowable operations cannot be extrapolated from the problem.
Discussing this issue, Rittel and Webber (1974) suggest that science and
engineering are dealing with well-structured or tame problems. But this
stance is not applicable to open social systems. Still, many social science
professionals have mimicked the cognitive style of scientists and the
operational style of engineers. But social problems are inherently wicked
problems. Thus, every solution of a wicked problem is tentative and incomplete,
and it changes as we move toward the solution. As the solution changes,
as it is elaborated, so does our understanding of the problem. Considering
this issue in the context of systems design, Rittel suggests that the
"ill-behaved" nature of design problem situations frustrates
all attempts to start out with an information and analysis phase, at the
end of which a clear definition of the problem is rendered and objectives
are defined that become the basis for synthesis, during which a "monastic"
solution can be worked out. Systems design requires a continuous interaction
between the initial phase that triggers design and the state when design
is completed.
3.1.8 The Soft-Systems Approach and Systems Design
From the 70s on, it was generally realized that the nature of issues
in human/social systems is "soft" in contrast with "hard"
issues and problems in systems engineering and other quantitative focused
systems inquiry.
Hard-systems thinking and approaches were not usable in the
context of human activity systems. "It is impossible to start the
studies by naming 'the system' and defining its objectives, and without
this naming/definition, hard systems thinking collapses" (Checkland,
198 1; Checkland and Scholes, 1990).
Churchman in his various works (1968a, 1968b, 1971, 1979, 1981) has been
the most articulate and most effective advocate of ethical systems theory
and morality in human systems inquiry. Human systems inquiry, Churchman
says, has to be value oriented, and it must be guided by the social imperative,
which dictates that technological efficiency must be subordinated to social
efficiency. He speaks for a science of values and the development of methods
by which to verify ethical judgments. He took issue (Churchman, 1971)
with the design approach where the focus is on various segments of the
system. When the designer detects a problem in a part, he moves to modify
it. This approach is based on the separability principle of incrementalism.
He advocates "nonseperabilty" when the application of decision
rules depends on the state of the whole system, and when a certain degree
of instability of a part occurs, the designer can recognize this event
and change the system so that the part becomes stable. "It can be
seen that design, properly viewed, is an enormous liberation of the intellectual
spirit, for it challenges this spirit to an unbounded speculation about
possibilities" (p. 13). A liberated designer will look at present
practice as a point of departure at best. Design is a thought process
and a communication process. Successful design is one that enables someone
to transfer thought into action or into another design.
Checkland (1981) and Checkland and Scholes (1990) developed a methodology
based on soft-systems thinking for working with human activity systems.
They consider the methodology as:
a learning system which uses systems ideas to formulate basic
mental acts of four kinds: perceiving, predicating, comparing, and deciding
for action. The output of the methodology is very different from the output
of systems engineering: It is learning which leads to decision to take
certain actions, knowing that this will lead not to "the problem"
being now "solved," but to a changed situation and new learning"
(1981, p. 17).
The methodology defined here is a direct consequence of the concept,
human activity system. We attribute meaning to all human activity. Our
attributions are meaningful in terms of our particular image of the world,
which, in general, we take for granted.
Systems design, in the context of social systems, is a future-creative
disciplined inquiry. People engage in this inquiry to design a system
that realizes their vision of the future, their own expectations, and
the expectations of their environment. Systems design is a relatively
new intellectual technology. It emerged only recently as a manifestation
of open-system thinking and corresponding ethically based soft-systems
approaches. This new intellectual technology emerged, just in time, as
a disciplined inquiry that enables us to align our social systems with
the new realities of the information/knowledge age (Banathy, 1991).
Early pioneers of social systems design include: Simon (1969), Jones
(1970), Churchman (1968, 1971, 1978), Jantsch (1976, 1980), Warfield (1976),
and Sage (1977). The watershed year of comprehensive statements on systems
design was 1981, marked by the works of Ackoff, Cbeckland, and Nadler.
Then came the work of Argyris (1982), Uhich (1983), Cross (1984), Morgan
(1986), Senge (1990), Warfield (1990), Nadler and Hibino (1990), Checkland
and Scholes (1990), Banadiy (1991), Hammer and Champy (1993), and Mitroff
and Linstone (1993).
Prior to the emergence of social systems design, the improvement approach
to systems change manifested traditional social planning (Banathy, 1991).
This approach, still practiced today, reduces the problem to manageable
pieces and seeks solutions to each. Users of this approach believe that
solving the problem piece by piece ultimately will correct the larger
issue it aims to remedy. But systems designers know that "getting
rid of what is not wanted does not give you what is desired." In
sharp contrast with traditional social planning, systems design-represented
by the authors above-seeks to understand the problem situation as a system
of interdependent and interacting problems, and seeks to create a design
as a system of interdependent and interacting solution ideas. Systems
designers envision the entity to be designed as a whole, as one that is
designed from the synthesis of the interaction of its parts. Systems design
requires both coordination and integration. We need to design all parts
of the system interactively and simultaneously. This requires coordination,
and designing for interdependency across all systems levels invites integration.
3.1.9 Reflections
In the first part of this chapter, systems inquiry was defined, and the
evolution of the systems movement was reviewed. Then we focused on human
systems inquiry, which is the conceptual foundation of the development
of a systems view and systems applications in education. As we reflect
on the ideas presented in this part, we realize how little of what was
discussed here has any serious manifestation or application in education.
Therefore, the second part of this chapter is devoted to the exploration
of a systems view of education and its practical applications in working
with systems of learning and human development.